Loading Session...

International Network for Economic Method (INEM)

Session Information

Modality and How-Possibly Explanations in Economics


Short summary (180)

There is a growing interest concerning the modal features of modelling across the sciences, with

economics being no exception. Economic modelling practices do not fit the procrustean bed of

full how-actually explanations and the demanding criteria on models that come with it. Instead of

dismissing these practices as epistemically inert, more effort must be invested in investigating

the role they play in establishing modal claims and providing how-possibly explanations.

However, we still have a limited understanding of how how-possibly explanations are formed

and used in practice and of their relationship with how-actually explanations. We also lack


methodological criteria that would help us to assess the epistemic and heuristic value of how-

possibly explanations.


This session aims to make three chief contributions. First, we show that the practice of

establishing modal claims is well entrenched in the practice of economists, even those with an

eye on policy. Second, we illuminate how how-possibly explanations relate to economic

modelling practices and how they are used to acquire how-actually explanations of phenomena

of interest. Third, we provide methodological resources to appraise how-possibly explanations in

economics.


Topic description (991)

How we can learn about the world with highly idealized models has been a vexing philosophical

issue. These models often do not faithfully describe the world as it is, yet it also seems they are

not epistemically vacuous. Philosophers have started to draw attention to the modal features of

scientific modelling (e.g. Betz 2015; Bokulich 2014; Knuuttila and Koskinen 2020; Massimi

2019; Rice 2016; Shech and Gelfert 2019; Weisberg 2013). According to that growing body of

literature, scientists sometimes seek to establish possibility claims. For instance, biologists

synthesize potential organisms (Elowitz and Lim 2010) and physicists model impossible

perpetual motion machines (Feynman, Leighton, and Sands 2010) to further our understanding of

the world. They pursue the epistemic goals of science by inquiring into the possible and

impossible.

We observe a similar interest concerning economic models. They are sometimes said to describe

credible worlds (Sugden 2000, 2009), establish possibility claims to rebut impossibility ones

(Grüne-Yanoff 2009), or provide how-possibly explanations (Aydinonat 2007, 2008; Ylikoski

and Aydinonat 2014). All this draws attention to the modal features of economic modelling

(Hausman 1984; Rappaport 1986, 1989, 1998): economics pursues not only its aims by

investigating what is actual, but also what is possible. Moreover, while some philosophers of

economics are pessimistic about the capacities of economic models to accurately represent the

actual world and explain (Alexandrova and Northcott 2013), others have suggested that they

might fare better as representations of genuine possibilities (Grüne-Yanoff 2013; Verreault-

Julien 2017; Ylikoski and Aydinonat 2014), thus offering an alternative and nuanced vindication

of current economic modelling practices.


The methodology of economics needs this nuance. Prediction and explanation are commonly

considered as the most important goals of economic modelling. Yet, typical accounts of

economic modelling that rely on representational adequacy and robustness as criteria for success

suggest that most economic models fail to achieve these goals (Aydinonat and Köksal 2019). It is

true that economic models often do not meet the decomposability assumptions needed for

minimalist accounts of idealization (Cartwright 2009; Grüne-Yanoff 2011) and that most of them

are not robust to many kinds of de-idealizations (Knuuttila and Morgan 2019). Thus, they are

unlikely candidates for providing good predictions or explanations. But it does not follow from

this that most economic modelling is deficient. The reason is that the dominant accounts of

economic modelling do not do much justice to practice of economic modelling and particularly

to its modal features. Before dismissing these practices as epistemically inert, one must invest

more effort in investigating the role models play in establishing modal claims and providing

how-possibly explanations.

However, we currently have a limited understanding of modal modelling. No systematic survey

of modal modelling practices in economics exists, and few proposals have been offered how to

categorize and systematize these practices. Nor are there clear analyses of the epistemic

contributions of economic modal modelling. Do they consist in how-possibly explanations that

have epistemic value in their own right, or do they indirectly contribute to how-actually

explanations, and only through that acquire value? Furthermore, we also lack methodological

criteria for assessing the quality of specific how-possibly explanations.

This session focusses on those modelling practices that relate to how-possibly explanations. It

consists of three papers that examine distinct features of how-possibly explanations in

economics. Each paper documents some specific modal modelling practices in economics,

ranging from central bank modelling through trade theory to modelling cooperation. Each paper

then analyses how these practices make a substantial epistemic contribution, and concludes by

identifying criteria for assessing the quality of these modal modelling practices.

The first paper focusses on models considered potential candidates for providing causal

explanations, as one finds them, e.g., in central bank multi-model platforms. When considered on

their own, these models merely provide 'thin' how-possibly explanations of little epistemic

value. Yet, in practice, these models are crucial for acquiring how-actually explanations. The

paper illustrates such practices by showing how the Bank of England integrates multiple how-

possibly models in its COMPASS platform, aiming at how-actually explanation of real-world 

phenomena, and it investigates the success conditions of such how-actually explanations in terms

of how well they facilitate reasoning about reliable intervention.

The second paper emphasizes that economists often make use of multiple models along with

other sources of information in their quest for explaining actual phenomena. Therefore,

individual models rarely function as explanantia. Rather, economists typically use a set of

models (each of them highly idealized) to construct a 'menu' of possible explanations,

viz. explanations whose truth isn't yet established. When doing so, they rely on a diversity of

models and sources of evidence. Determining the actual explanation is then a matter of

eliminating the possible candidate explanations and establishing the truth of the relevant

explanantia.

The third paper argues that the practice of providing 'mere' how-possibly explanations does not

entitle economists to formulate any just-so story they wish. It proposes a conceptual framework

that allows assessing 'good' from 'bad' how-possibly explanations. This conceptual framework

relies on two key distinctions: the first between how-actually and how-possibly explanations, the

second between epistemic and objective how-possibly explanations. It argues that both of these

latter categories afford their own epistemically relevant results, and both have the conceptual

resources to distinguish between good and bad models. The paper illustrates these arguments

with examples from trade theory, economic geography, and social cooperation.

With these three presentations, the session aims to further our understanding of how-possibly

explanations and modal modelling in economics. In particular, we pursue three goals. First, we

show that the practice of establishing modal claims is well entrenched in the modelling strategies

of economists, even those with an eye on policy. Second, we illuminate how how-possibly

explanations make substantial epistemic contributions, either by establishing relevant free-

standing modal claims or by facilitating, in conjunction with other sources of information, the

development of how-actually explanations of phenomena of interest. Third, we provide

methodological guidelines for assessing the quality of how-possibly explanations, thus showing

that they are distinct from methodologically naive just-so stories.

11 Nov 2021 08:30 AM - 10:00 AM(America/New_York)
Venue : Key Ballroom 09
20211111T0830 20211111T1000 America/New_York International Network for Economic Method (INEM)

Modality and How-Possibly Explanations in Economics

Short summary (180)

There is a growing interest concerning the modal features of modelling across the sciences, with

economics being no exception. Economic modelling practices do not fit the procrustean bed of

full how-actually explanations and the demanding criteria on models that come with it. Instead of

dismissing these practices as epistemically inert, more effort must be invested in investigating

the role they play in establishing modal claims and providing how-possibly explanations.

However, we still have a limited understanding of how how-possibly explanations are formed

and used in practice and of their relationship with how-actually explanations. We also lack

methodological criteria that would help us to assess the epistemic and heuristic value of how-

possibly explanations.

This session aims to make three chief contributions. First, we show that the practice of

establishing modal claims is well entrenched in the practice of economists, even those with an

eye on policy. Second, we illuminate how how-possibly explanations relate to economic

modelling practices and how they are used to acquire how-actually explanations of phenomena

of interest. Third, w ...

Key Ballroom 09 PSA 2020/2021 office@philsci.org

Presentations

The Needle in the Haystack: Finding the Actual Amongst the Possible

Cognate Society Session 08:30 AM - 10:00 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 13:30:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 15:00:00 UTC
The status of economic models is a bit peculiar. It’s commonly recognized that all such models
incorporate idealizations or abstractions, and so they seem divorced from the real-world target
systems they are meant to be informative about. More specifically, they seem to do quite poorly
in terms of representing their targets.
Whatever one learns about the model, this knowledge only carries over to knowledge about the
target system if the appropriate kinds of relationships hold between the two. The strongest form
of this relation is isomorphism; given that this standard is unrealistic, authors have spoken more
nebulously of “similarity relations” of the relevant sort à la Giere (1988, 2006). This has ushered
in a literature that conceptually distinguishes models from their targets by relegating models into
the realm of “credible worlds” (Sugden 2000, 2009) which might be able to enable “surrogative
reasoning” (Swoyer 1991). Even these maneuvers, however, leave an epistemic gap: when is a
bit of surrogative reasoning good? Others conceive of models as the kinds of tools that might
lack targets altogether, or provide epistemic insight despite not being about anything in the “real
world”.
This paper argues the following. First, models – when even they are conceived as targetless – can
only give very thin kinds of how-possibly explanations when considered on their own. I will
focus my attention on models that are potential candidates for providing causal explanations –
therefore, I do not address models that might do different things for different purposes, such as
reduced-form models for forecasting. But, I suggest that in practice, such thin how-possibly
models are integral stepping-stones that guide the construction of how-actually models. I argue
that part of the policymaker’s job is to find out when such hypothetical claims actually do hold –
that is, when the conditions stipulated by the models are instantiated (to a good approximation)
in the real world – a process that, despite philosophers turning away from isomorphism talk,
aims to recover the relevant isomorphic relations indexed to the particular size and time scale of
the economic system in question.


However, models do not generally fit their purported real-world targets out of the box. In
practice, the idealized model serves as an initial benchmark or baseline template. Using the
example of central bank modelling, in particular focusing on how the Bank of England integrates
multiple models into its central COMPASS platform, I show how it is that central banks try to
attain how-actually explanation from several models, all of which are in some sense idealized
and therefore themselves providers of how-possibly explanations. I spell out the success
conditions of such how-actually explanations in terms of how well they facilitate reasoning about
reliable intervention, relying on Chang’s (2016) notion of “pragmatic coherence” and more
recent (2017) work on “pragmatic realism”.
Presenters
JJ
Jennifer Jhun
Duke University

Economic Models and Possible Explanation

Cognate Society Session 08:30 AM - 10:00 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 13:30:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 15:00:00 UTC
What do we mean when we say that an economic model provides a how-possibly explanation
(HPE)? And, what does it mean when we say that an economic model explains? One way to
answer the second question is to say that a model explains if “the explanans [...] makes an
essential reference to” the model (Bokulich 2011, 38). There are two difficulties with this view.
First, it does not acknowledge the fact that economists often use multiple models to explain
(Aydinonat 2018; Rodrik 2015). Second, it leaves out the many ways in which models are
explanatorily useful (i.e., many ways in which they can contribute to explanations). These two
difficulties relate to the question about HPEs. As Bokulich (2014) argues, accounts of HPEs do
not pay sufficient attention to the importance of explanatory context and the level of abstraction.
I follow Bokulich (2014) with the following amendments. I argue that this is in fact a more
general problem that cripples our understanding of how idealised models help explain. I suggest
taking into account the fact that multiple models could contribute to one explanation. To be able
to do this, I recommend carefully separating our talk about models from our claims concerning
explanation and eliminating elliptical formulations such as the ‘explanandum of a model’. I
argue, in line with many other accounts, that models help economists answer what-if questions
about the model worlds they have constructed (e.g., Morgan 2012; Ylikoski 2009; Ylikoski and
Aydinonat 2014; Ylikoski and Kuorikoski 2010). This is how economists learn about what
would actually happen in their model worlds and about the possibilities that are present in their
models with respect to difference makers. A common practice in economics is to use this
knowledge to formulate a set of possible explanations: candidate answers for the explanatory
question at hand. Based on this practice, I argue that the explanatory value of many idealised
models in economics could be understood in terms of the contribution they make to the menu of
possible explanations available to them (Aydinonat 2018; Ylikoski and Aydinonat 2014). For
brevity, I explicate this claim by focusing on singular explanations. To come up with a menu of
possible of explanations economists often make use of multiple models along with other sources
of information (Aydinonat 2018; Aydinonat and Köksal 2019; Ylikoski and Aydinonat 2014).
The "possible" in “possible explanations” can range from mere logical possibilities to causal and
factual possibilities. As a result, to understand how idealised models explain and make sense of
their modal features one needs to look at how economists actually use their models to explain in
the context of relevant models and available evidence. The paper illustrates these points with
three examples from economics: a supply-demand model, a location model, and a simple
monopoly model. I also show that such possible explanations are often HPEs in a loose
Hempelian sense (Hempel 1965; Verreault-Julien 2019). Finding the true explanation is therefore
a matter of eliminating possible explanations and establishing the truth of the explanantia.

How-Possibly Explanations in Economics: Anything Goes?

Cognate Society Session 08:30 AM - 10:00 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 13:30:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 15:00:00 UTC
Modelling practices are pervasive in economics, yet the current methodological literature tends
to assign epistemic value to economic models only to the extent that they provide predictions or
explanations of actual phenomena. It confines other modelling practices to their “heuristic”,
pedagogical or otherwise non-epistemic uses.
In this paper, we argue to the contrary that at least some of these “other” modelling practices do
have epistemic value and can be subject to systematic methodological assessment. For this
argument, we draw two key distinctions: first, between how-actually explanations (HAE) and
how-possibly explanations (HPE), familiar from the extant literature. And, secondly, between
epistemic and objective how-possibly explanations, depending on whether the modalities
employed in the HPE are epistemic or objective possibilities. With these two distinctions, we
analyze modelling practices in trade theory, economic geography, and social cooperation.
We begin by analyzing Krugman’s (1979) trade model, which represented sustained international
trade even between countries that exhibited no comparative advantages. This constituted
epistemic progress in economics because the model could accommodate existing trade data in a
more consistent way than previous models could. Nevertheless, there was little evidence
supporting the posited key drivers of this model, increasing returns to scale and monopolistic
competition, as the actual causes of these observed patterns. Instead, the posited drivers were not
ruled out by contemporary knowledge and thus epistemically possible.
We contrast such successful epistemic HPEs with the debate and opposition that other epistemic
HPEs have triggered. What is so different about them? Take Krugman’s (1991) core-periphery
model (C-P model). In some broad sense, it is surely a possible explanation of location
phenomena. But the devil is in the details. Critics point to extensive empirical investigations and
argue that the complexities of location decisions cannot be captured with the C-P model. Thus,
the quality of HPE explanations depends on their consistency with all relevant knowledge; HPEs
consistent only with selected knowledge are generally not admissible.
Yet, not all HPEs focus on actual phenomena and offer accounts consistent with all relevant
knowledge. Our analysis of Axelrod et al.’s (2002) social cooperation modelling shows that such
models typically make substantial counterfactual assumptions that cannot be justified as
approximations or tractability assumptions, but instead depict explanantia that appear
inconsistent with what we know about the actual world. These are thus not epistemic HPEs.
Nevertheless, they play important epistemic functions: they aim to track objective, often
counterfactual, relevant possibilities. We, therefore, call them objective HPEs. What possibilities
are relevant often depends on context, but a clear example is when a widely shared belief in an
impossibility can thus be adjusted. Many economic models do not meet either the condition of
consistency with objective constraints or the relevance conditions — and therefore are generally
not admissible as objective HPEs.
Our paper thus shows that the practice of providing ‘mere’ how-possibly explanations doesn’t
entitle economists to formulate any just-so story they wish. It identifies various epistemic uses of
HPEs, and offers a conceptual framework that allows distinguishing ‘good’ from ‘bad’ ones.
Presenters
TG
Till Grüne-Yanoff
KTH Royal Institute Of Technology, Stockholm
587 visits

Session Participants

User Online
Session speakers, moderators & attendees
Duke University
University of Helsinki
KTH Royal Institute of Technology, Stockholm
 Seán Muller
University of Johannesburg
 Peter Sauter
Boston University
CNRS Univ. Bordeaux
 Karim Bschir
University of St. Gallen, Switzerland
28 attendees saved this session

Session Chat

Live Chat
Chat with participants attending this session

Need Help?

Technical Issues?

If you're experiencing playback problems, try adjusting the quality or refreshing the page.

Questions for Speakers?

Use the Q&A tab to submit questions that may be addressed in follow-up sessions.