Loading Session...

Society for Philosophy and Psychology (SPP)

Session Information

Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives on Explanation


This symposium will feature five projects at the intersection of philosophy and psychology

exploring the structure and content of explanation. The contributors will address philosophical

questions about how explanations are constructed and interpreted in light of psychological

findings about scientific cognition. The symposium will consist of five 15-minute talks, with

three minutes following each talk for questions.


Sara Aronowitz will begin the symposium with a discussion of structural constraints on

explanation, arguing that satisfying explanations contain not just abstract, semantic structure but

also experiential, temporal structure. Daniel Wilkenfeld, Richard Samuels, and James Fritz will

then explore the structure of a particular kind of explanation-mathematical explanation-by

probing psychological attitudes about the truth of mathematical statements and the existence of

mathematical entities. Next, Elizabeth Bonawitz will present an interdisciplinary model of

scientific reasoning, demonstrating how explanatory activities are constrained by cognitive

engagement, via questions and thought experiments, as well as cognitive emotions, like

uncertainty and surprise. David Danks will then present a model of theory discovery, arguing

that cognitive science provides a precedent for at least two rational (logic-based) pathways of

discovery: automated discovery via machine learning and deliberative discovery via theory-

based inference. Andrew Shtulman will conclude the symposium by exploring the question of

what happens to folk explanations of natural phenomena when we acquire scientific explanations

of the same phenomena and whether we can learn to privilege the latter over the former.

Collectively, these talks will highlight the interplay of psychology and philosophy in

constraining and testing current theories of explanation.

11 Nov 2021 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM(America/New_York)
Venue : Key Ballroom 01
20211111T1015 20211111T1145 America/New_York Society for Philosophy and Psychology (SPP)

Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives on Explanation

This symposium will feature five projects at the intersection of philosophy and psychology

exploring the structure and content of explanation. The contributors will address philosophical

questions about how explanations are constructed and interpreted in light of psychological

findings about scientific cognition. The symposium will consist of five 15-minute talks, with

three minutes following each talk for questions.

Sara Aronowitz will begin the symposium with a discussion of structural constraints on

explanation, arguing that satisfying explanations contain not just abstract, semantic structure but

also experiential, temporal structure. Daniel Wilkenfeld, Richard Samuels, and James Fritz will

then explore the structure of a particular kind of explanation-mathematical explanation-by

probing psychological attitudes about the truth of mathematical statements and the existence of

mathematical entities. Next, Elizabeth Bonawitz will present an interdisciplinary model of

scientific reasoning, demonstrating how explanatory activities are constrained by cognitive

engagement, via questions and thought experiments, as well as cognitive emotions, like

uncertainty and surprise. David Danks will then present a model of theory discovery, arguing

that cognitive science provides a precedent for at least two rational (logic-based) pathways of

discovery: automated discovery via machine learning and deliberative discovery via theory-

based inference. Andrew Shtulman will conclude the symposium by exploring the question of

what happens to folk explanations of natural phenomena when we acquire scientific ex ...

Key Ballroom 01 PSA 2020/2021 office@philsci.org

Presentations

Multiple Cognitive Structures: When and Why?

Cognate Society Session 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 15:15:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 16:45:00 UTC
An explanation conveys content according to a structure. For example, as a child I
was preoccupied with this question: why does your reflection in the mirror seem reversed from
left-to-right and not from top-to-bottom? I might now answer by describing how we are attentive
to some ways of moving our bodies more than others, and then linking this fact to the experience
of looking in a mirror. In this explanation, I’ve conveyed an answer to the question in a particular
way: through a general fact about perception of motion, combined with a specific story bridging
between the general fact and the case at hand. This latter element is the explanatory structure: the
bones of an explanation, so to speak. I might have answered the mirror question with a different
structure: providing an explanation that relies crucially on visualization by acting out the
different ways of “stepping into” the mirror. These two explanations may even in some sense
provide the same answer, but through different means.
My project explores cases where more than one explanatory structure is at work, treating
these structures as members of a broader family of cognitive structures. What does it mean for
structure, rather than contents, to differ, and how do structures of different types interact in
learning? I focus on cases where a single learning problem is solved with more than one
structure, where this means not merely two different contents but two ways of presenting content
that differ with respect to the way they organize information.
I'll present two cases of contrasting structures, from the domains of explanation and
memory, using both experimental and theoretical techniques to ground a hypothesis about what
these structures are and why we might need more than one of them. (1) In response to
why-questions, people offer both narrative and abstract explanations. These two structures, I'll
argue, work together to allow us to understand and communicate - and data from adult learners
suggests that both structures are in some sense equally explanatory. (2) In memory, spatial (and
spatio-temporal) map-like structures have been posited to extend to all kinds of knowledge
domains beyond the literally spatial. But what is lost when we extend the concept of a map this
far?
In both cases, an experiential, temporal structure works alongside a more allocentric,
semantic structure. But this symmetry papers over deeper differences in function. On my view,
the narrative/abstract dichotomy in explanation, and the episodic/semantic one in memory
display the same general trade-off between flexibility and strength of structure, though they
differ structurally in many significant ways.
Putting these cases together, we see that even simple learning problems are not best
solved by finding the "right" structure, but instead require a more complex array of structures.
This is a clue to the utility of multiple, distinct, explanatory structures.
Presenters
SA
Sara Aronowitz
Princeton University

A Nonfictional Look at Mathematical Fictionalism

Cognate Society Session 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 15:15:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 16:45:00 UTC
Mathematics has long been a source of philosophical puzzlement. On the one hand, the truth of
mathematical statements, such as (1), would seem to require the existence of mathematical
objects:
(1) There are prime numbers less than 10.
On the other hand, such objects —if they exist— seem very strange by common standards:
apparently acausal and lacking spatiotemporal location.
Mathematical fictionalists respond to the above predicament by accepting the conditional that if
mathematical statements are true, then mathematical objects exist, while also denying that such
objects exist and, hence, that mathematical statements are true. In this talk we discuss variants
of fictionalism – hermeneutic mathematical fictionalisms (HMFs) – which incur commitments
regarding the psychological attitudes expressed by speakers when uttering mathematical
statements like (1).
To a first approximation, all HMFs maintain that when speakers utter mathematical statements,
they seldom, if ever, express prototypical beliefs of the sort expressed by assertions of empirical
fact. On this view, for example, an utterance of (1) seldom, if ever, expresses the belief that
there are prime numbers less than 10. Some versions maintain that another attitude –
sometimes called ‘acceptance’ -- is expressed by utterances like (1). Others suggest that the
attitude expressed is belief, but that the contents of the belief diverges from the apparent
meaning of the mathematical statement. Crudely put, it is in some way figurative, fictive, or
otherwise non-literal. Crucially, all such views incur empirical commitments regarding the
psychological attitudes of speakers.
Given that HMFs incur such commitments, one would expect it to yield broadly behavioral
predictions that diverge from those associated with the hypothesis that utterances of
mathematical statements express literal belief. In view of this, we explore the extent to which
some variants of HMF make such contrastive predictions. In doing so, we first note that some
views appear too vague to yield determinate predictions. We then present some preliminary
empirical results regarding more perspicuous versions of HMF to see whether their predictions
are borne out.
We conclude by suggesting that this preliminary study may provide a template for studying other
views in the philosophy of science which incur commitments regarding psychological attitudes.
Specifically, we suggest that analogous research may be relevant to some familiar issues in the
literature on scientific realism.
Presenters
DW
Daniel Wilkenfeld
University Of Pittsburgh
RS
Richard Samuels
JF
James Fritz

Engaging mental models in prediction and explanation to support learning in early childhood

Cognate Society Session 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 15:15:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 16:45:00 UTC
Multiple accounts of human learning exist, each suggesting multiple routes for encoding of
information. One often contrasted aspect of learning involves whether the route involves
“bottom-up” associative mechanisms, or top-down, model-based approach. In model-based
approaches, the learner is actively constructing predictions of possible worlds while engaging in
inference. As much past research has highlighted, which kind of learning is engaged can
depend on working memory, processing speed, and the agent’s prior knowledge. But less work
has focused on how the same kind of content might be learned differently, depending on
whether or not a learners “mental models” are engaged, nor have factors like explanation and
prediction been explicitly linked to these different processes in neurology, physiology, and
behavior. In this talk, I will discuss several lines of research pointing to the role of explanation
and prediction as key tools in helping children engage in “model-based” learning in causal,
scientific thought. The research presented will bring together computational models with
neurological, physiological, and behavioral data in infants, preschoolers, and early elementary
school children, to provide an integrated account of the role of model building through
prediction and explanation in learning.
Specifically, the first study will present emerging evidence from our lab employing a
neurological marker of uncertainty and active learning (theta response); our preliminary results
(N=34 infants) provide evidence for infant’s (M=16mos) sensitivity to causally confounded and
unconfounded events through differing theta response (co authored Begus). This work suggests
that even infants are sensitive to uncertainty in causal explanatory events and engaging in
“mental preparation” for explanatory content. The second study will focus on how engaging
preschoolers (N=72) to “self-explain” a causal event (as prompted through pedagogical
questions in a three-week training study) leads to better learning, generalization, and memory
of scientific content in the biological domain, as compared to preschoolers who passively listen
to the content or a control group (co-authored Daubert, Yu, Shafto). This work suggests the role
of self-explanation in helping engage the learner in model building and learning. The third study
explores the role of “thought experiments” (self-generated explanatory, predictive models) in


helping (6-7 year-old) learners engage in conceptual change in the physical domain (co-
authored Bascandziev). The fourth study presents a computational model that predicts surprise


based on a learner’s prior beliefs and the evidence observed, and then compares the model to
a physiological measure commonly suggested to capture surprise: pupil dilation. In this final, I


present evidence that a computational model integrating beliefs and evidence predicts school-
aged children's (N=95, aged 6-9 years-old) surprise of a water-displacement event. Critically,


this prediction only bears out when participants were encouraged to predict an outcome prior
to observing it, suggesting the critical role of explanatory, top-down model building in surprise
and belief revision (co-authored Brod, Theobald, Bascandziev, Colantonio). Taken together, this
work will support the claim that learning is supported by active prediction and explanation by
engaging top-down, model-based mechanisms.

Rational scientific theory discovery

Cognate Society Session 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 15:15:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 16:45:00 UTC
The processes by which we discover or develop novel scientific theories is sometimes argued to
fall outside of the scope of rationality; most famously, Popper argued that there was no “logic of
scientific discovery.” In this talk, I will argue that there are at least two different paths by which we
can (and do) rationally discover novel scientific theories. One route is through the use of automated
discovery methods from data and phenomena, including modern machine learning algorithms. A
second route is through rational reasoning grounded in the intertheoretic constraints imposed by
other (tentatively accepted) scientific theories. For each pathway, I will give examples of rational
theory discovery within cognitive science to argue that considerations of rationality play a role in the
actual scientific reasoning practices.
Given these two different (potentially) rational discovery pathways, I will then consider the
explanations provided by each. In particular, the first pathway principally yields theories that can
explain patterns in our data and phenomena, while the second pathway primarily leads to theories
that can explain the content of, and connections between, disparate elements of scientific theory. Of
course, a novel theory that results from either pathway can potentially provide explanations of the
other type, but only after additional scientific effort. I (re)use the cognitive science examples to
vividly illustrate this difference in explanatory target. Finally, I argue—in light of the pragmatic,
future-directed nature of explanations—for a “meta-rationality” constraint on scientific theory
discovery: namely, our selection of one rational method (rather than another) is itself subject to
rational evaluation.
Presenters
DD
David Danks
University Of California, San Diego

Navigating the Conflict Between Science and Intuition

Cognate Society Session 10:15 AM - 11:45 AM (America/New_York) 2021/11/11 15:15:00 UTC - 2021/11/11 16:45:00 UTC
Before learning scientific theories, we form intuitive theories of the same phenomena. Intuitive
theories provide us with explanations and predictions, like scientific theories, but they rely on
categories that play no role in science. In the domain of biology, for instance, children intuitively
identify life with self-directed motion, leading to the misconception that sun and the clouds are
alive but plants are not. In physics, children intuitively identify matter with perceivability,
yielding the misconception that heat and light are material substances but gasses are not.
In this presentation, I will explore how intuitive theories of life and matter automatically
compete with their scientific successors, as revealed by a statement-verification task. Participants
are asked to verify scientific statements as quickly as possible. Some statements are consistent
with intuitive theories, such as “tigers are alive,” which is both scientifically true and intuitively
true, or “rocks are alive, which is both scientifically false and intuitively false. Other statements
are inconsistent with intuitive theories, such as “oaks are alive,” which is scientifically true but
intuitively false, or “the sun is alive,” which is scientifically false but intuitively true. Across
concepts and domains, the latter type of statement is verified less accurately and more slowly
than the former, indicating that intuitive theories are not erased by scientific theories but coexist
with them instead, yielding internal conflict when the two theories provide divergent inferences
or interpretations.
Using this paradigm, we have found the people can learn to verify scientific statements more
accurately, but they cannot learn to verify them more quickly. Scientists verify scientific
statements more accurately than non-scientists but still take longer to verify counterintuitive
statements relative to intuitive ones. Priming people to think more scientifically, with diagrams
and models, increases response accuracy but has no effect on response times. The same holds for
training people to think more scientifically, by providing targeted instruction in the relevant
domain. Instruction increases the accuracy of participants’ verifications but has little effect on
speed. That is, instruction shrinks the gap between intuitive and counterintuitive statements in
terms of how accurately they are verified but does not affect the gap in how quickly they are
verified. This finding holds for both adults and children, even preschool-aged children who are
just beginning to construct scientific theories of the natural world.
The finding that accuracy is malleable when reasoning about counterintuitive scientific ideas but
speed is not suggests that intuitive theories are activated automatically by the phenomena they
were meant to explain, even for those practiced at reasoning scientifically. They also suggest that
science education should not focus on erasing intuitive theories or resolving the conflict between
intuitive and scientific theories but should instead focus on providing skills to prioritize science
over intuition. Such skills include inhibitory control, set-shifting ability, and cognitive reflection,
all of which have been shown to facilitate scientific reasoning in contexts where students are
prone to rely on pre-scientific intuitions instead.
Presenters
AS
Andrew Shtulman
Occidental College
463 visits

Session Participants

User Online
Session speakers, moderators & attendees
Princeton University
University of Pittsburgh
University of California, San Diego
+ 1 more speakers. View All
Occidental College
No attendee has checked-in to this session!
34 attendees saved this session

Session Chat

Live Chat
Chat with participants attending this session

Need Help?

Technical Issues?

If you're experiencing playback problems, try adjusting the quality or refreshing the page.

Questions for Speakers?

Use the Q&A tab to submit questions that may be addressed in follow-up sessions.